Introduction
At first sight, the act of doing as the role model does may appear to be a fairly uncontroversial aspect of emulation, yet on closer conceptual inspection things are somewhat more complicated. Zagzebski, for example, who has been considered an authority on moral exemplarism (see 2017), takes emulation to be a ‘form of behaviour’ (2015, p. 210), yet in doing so limits its scope to merely this. She posits the positively experienced emotion of admiration as the primary motivation for emulation, a reading which she ‘assumes’ to be similar to Aristotle’s reading of the emotion of emulation in Rhetoric (2013; 2015; 2017). The thing is that in Rhetoric (2001, p. 75) Aristotle describes emulation as an overall negatively experienced emotion, combining both the feeling of admiration and the feeling of distress, which is ‘caused by seeing the presence, in persons whose nature is like our own, of good things that are highly valued and are possible for ourselves to acquire’ – something which calls Zagzebski’s similarity assumption into question. Indeed, whilst Zagzebski’s Exemplarist Moral Theory (2017) should be credited for reviving the interest in exemplarism in multiple academic discourses, many scholars have voiced persuasive objections to her overemphasis on admiration at the expense of other important aspects of exemplarism – such as exemplarity-related negative emotions – which has begun to push it out of favour (see also Irwin, 2015, p. 247; Kaftanski, 2022; Szutta, 2019; Vaccarezza & Niccoli, 2019, p. 333; 2022, p. 112). All this said, perhaps Zagzebski was onto something important in her description of emulation as a form of behaviour, something which understanding emulation as merely an emotion excludes. Let me explain.
Inspired by Aristotle’s depiction of emulation (zélos) as an emotion in Rhetoric (2001, pp. 75-76) and Nicomachean Ethics (2009, 1180b3-8), most neo-Aristotelians also categorise emulation as an emotion (e.g., see Croce, 2019, p. 238; Kristjánsson, 2006, 2018; Sanderse, 2013, p. 36; Steutel & Spiecker, 2004, p. 545; Vaccarezza & Niccoli, 2022, p. 113; Vos, 2018, p. 6). Within virtue ethics, it is understood that virtuous emotions, i.e., emotions infused with practical wisdom (phronesis), are the central ingredients in virtue proper, yet the two are distinct in that virtuous action is a necessary condition of virtue, but not of virtuous emotion – a point which is reinforced by Aristotle and other eminent neo-Aristotelian scholars multiple times (e.g., see 2009, NE, 1098b30-1099a6; Rorty, 1984 , p. 535). More specifically, according to Kristjánsson’s componential account of virtuous emotions, they comprise: perception, thought (cognition), physiological feeling and a behavioural suggestion (Kristjánsson, 2018, p. 13). However, since proponents of neo-Aristotelian character education – a form of moral education rooted in virtue ethics – consider the emulation of moral role models to be a, possibly even the, central method of virtuous character development from infancy to early adulthood (e.g., see Croce & Vaccarezza, 2017; Kristjánsson, 2015; 2020; Vos, 2018), this means that emulation is explicitly associated with virtue development. Whilst this might seem like a truism, if one accepts Krisjánsson’s componential account of virtuous emotions, it is clear that they entail a behavioural suggestion, but not full virtuous activity, which is reserved only for virtue. Yet, if emulation concerns the development of virtue qua full virtue, then, as a matter of logical coherence, it must also include the activity of doing as the role model does, i.e., putting the moral ideals they represent into practice (Henderson, 2022). In addition to virtuous emotion, then, activity should be considered essential to being emulous.
This short foray into the emulation literature gives a flavour of the conceptual tensions which permeate the discourse. Indeed, despite the consensus that becoming virtuous requires the emulation of moral role models, as it stands, there exists a lack of clarity regarding what emulation involves and how the method works in classroom contexts (see Kristjánsson, 2020, p. 136; Vos, 2018) – indicating that questions regarding how role modelling does or should take place remain open. This paper seeks to disambiguate the process of emulation qua role modelling, by unpacking the concept of emulation itself. I argue that much of the ambiguity surrounding emulation lies in a category mistake: the misconceptualisation of emulation as a mere emotion rather than, as I will argue, a virtue in its own right (Section 1). I propose that understanding emulation as a virtue allows one to accommodate how becoming virtuous concerns both the cultivation of virtuous emotions and virtuous action under one conceptual umbrella. To further my thesis, I propose to add methodological rigour to emulation as a causal process by systematising it with Aristotle’s understanding of causation in his Metaphysics (1999, 1044a32-4): the four causes (Section 2). I then make visible the importance of phronesis to the emulative process and accordingly introduce a new concept – entangled phronesis – as the psycho-moral mechanism which underpins it (Section 3). Here, I also highlight the developmentally sensitive nature of emulation by dividing it into two main types: pre-phronetic habituated emulation and phronetically-informed complete emulation.
Before I proceed, I will take a moment to outline the scope which I intend this analysis of emulation qua role modelling to encompass. For reasons of space, I cannot go into as much depth as I would like, and thus direct readers to two recent papers which add further contours and nuance to the arguments I briefly summarise here (Henderson, 2022; 2023). Furthermore, it should be noted that whilst my position is inherently reconstructive rather than exegetical in nature, I maintain that synthesising much of what follows with Aristotle’s ethics and metaphysics can meaningfully extend the contemporary understanding of emulation in neo-Aristotelian character education. Finally, I broadly understand virtues – such as honesty, compassion and justice – as acquired stable traits of character, with character conceptualised as the ‘the integration of a constellation of virtues within personality’ (Wright et al., 2020, p. 9). Relatedly, phronesis is conceptualised in accordance with the Aristotelian Phronesis Model (Kristjánsson et al., 2021, p. 240-241), as ‘an intellectual meta-virtue of holistic, integrative, contextual, practical reflection and adjudication about moral issues, leading to moral action’.
1 Emulation as a moral virtue
Since I have already outlined the central tenets of this argument in the introduction (see also Henderson, 2022), I will now proceed to frame it in standard form:
- Virtuous emotions are components of virtues.
- Therefore, virtues and virtuous emotions are intrinsically related but distinct.
- Virtues are distinguished from virtuous emotions by activity, with virtuous activity being a necessary condition of virtue, but not of virtuous emotion.
- This entails that, in order to become virtuous, one must put virtuous emotions into practice by exercising virtuous activity.
- The central way to become virtuous is through emulating moral role models.
- This implies that, in addition to virtuous emotion, the emulation of role models must include activity.
- If emulation must include activity, it cannot be purely a virtuous emotion.
- Therefore, emulation is better categorised as a virtue.
It is worth noting that as Premise 5 is inductive and relies on empirical evidence, this is not purely a deductive argument and best my conclusion 8. can be highly probable. To make my argument as persuasive as possible, I shall now proceed to defend the most contentious premises, primarily 3, 4 and 6.
Premise 3: ‘virtues are distinguished from virtuous emotions by activity, with virtuous activity being a necessary condition of virtue, but not of virtuous emotion’, is supported both by Aristotle and his neo-Aristotelian sympathisers. Aristotle, for example, unambiguously suggests that virtue includes an explicitly behavioural component:
‘…to virtue belongs virtuous activity…one who has the activity will of necessity be acting and acting well. And as in the Olympic Games it is not the most beautiful and the strongest that are crowned but those who compete…so those who act win, and rightly win, the noble and the good things in life’ (2009, NE 1098b30-1099a6).
Something that he reinforces at numerous other junctures in his writing (e.g., see 1936, pp. a33-1103b1; 1103b20–32; 1104b13–15; 1105b5–10). This move is also supported by contemporary neo-Aristotelian philosophers and moral psychologists who all include a behavioural element in their quadripartite componential accounts of virtue (e.g., see Curren & Kotzee, 2014; Fowers et al., 2021; Morgan et al., 2017; Wright et al., 2020). It is also worth reflecting here that in Rhetoric Aristotle explains emotions in three ways, rather than four, (Aristotle, 2001, p. 55), which could be taken to support virtuous action as the distinguishing factor between virtuous emotions and virtues.
Rorty’s definition of virtue also makes visible that virtue includes action:
‘Virtue (arete) is that sort of active disposition (hexis) which sets a person to act or react in a mean, in situations involving choice (prohairesis), following reason (logos) as the person of practical wisdom (phronimos) does in matters concerning pathe and actions’ (1984, p. 535).
Pathe and actions. Rorty can be interpreted as following Aristotle and others in proposing that virtue must include both emotion (pathe) and action. Regarding the pathe element, she explicitly states that to contribute to virtue these emotions must be voluntary, appropriate and appropriately understood, i.e. deliberate, medial and rational (Rorty, 1984, p. 537). Regarding action, she further emphasises that ‘Aristotle characterises each of the virtues as dispositions to typical actions and reactions’ (Rorty, 1984, p. 537), whist maintaining there is a relationship between virtuous emotions and virtue (Rorty, 1984, p. 538). Taken together, these considerations uphold the intrinsic link between action and virtue, and therefore Premise 3.
Premise 4: ‘in order to become virtuous, one must put virtuous emotions into practice by exercising virtuous activity’. That virtuous activity evolves a virtuous emotion into a virtue is a point that appears to gain support from Aristotle himself. Indeed, in the Nicomachean Ethics he posits that the ‘the virtues are concerned with actions and passions [emotions]’ (1936, pp. 1104b13–15), which suggests that both action and dispositional emotion are necessary for virtue. Action alone is insufficient for virtue (1936, p. 1105a28), nor is an emotion a virtue (1936, p. 1105b29). In light of this, even if prosocial acts are in accordance with virtue, in order to be considered virtuous they must be performed when the agent is in ‘a certain condition’ (1936, p. 1105a30). This ‘certain condition’ can be interpreted as being primarily driven by dispositional medial cognitive emotions, which are infused with phronesis, which subsequently enables active choice. Importantly, Aristotle (1936) further claims that ‘virtue makes the goal correct, and practical wisdom makes what leads to it correct’ (NE, pp. 1144a8–9). I interpret this as supporting that moral virtue is a perfected disposition to act, driven by phronetically informed, i.e., virtuous, emotion.
Premise 6: ‘in addition to virtuous emotion, the emulation of role models must include activity’. Let us consider two situations, in the first a pre-phronesis or low-phronesis moral learner perceives the exemplar’s virtues as representative of a moral ideal; thinks that they are worthy of emulation, possible to acquire and deserved; physically feels the distress and zeal associated with one’s lack of the desired quality; and perhaps a suggestion to behaviour. Here the learner may start to acquire a virtuous emotion yet cannot be credited with the acquisition of virtue proper. This is partly due to the compelling account of habituation prophesised by Steutel and Spiecker—guided by a role model, virtue must be practiced frequently and consistently to facilitate virtue acquisition (Steutel & Spiecker, 2004). Now consider a second situation which involves a similar process, but instead the behavioural suggestion motivates the learner to practice virtuous action. Consequently, whilst it may be perfectly reasonable to conceive of virtuous emotions without behaviour, as emulation is explicitly associated with virtue development, the same cannot be said for virtue. This entails Premise 7: ‘if emulation must include activity, it cannot be purely a virtuous emotion’, and following this the conclusion, that in light of the required behavioural aspect, ‘emulation is better categorised as a virtue’.
Given the complexity of my argument, of which the present account is admittedly only a brief summary, it is worth reiterating it in plain English. Essentially, since emulation is already categorised as a virtuous emotion in the neo-Aristotelian literature, but since emulation must also include virtuous behaviour, conceptually it is more coherent to categorise it as a moral virtue in its own right. Those who define emulation purely as an emotion may thus be guilty of a category mistake. Further, only if emulation is understood as a virtue can one accommodate how becoming virtuous concerns both the cultivation of virtuous emotions and virtuous action under one conceptual umbrella. Having briefly justified my argument in favour of conceptualising emulation as a moral virtue, I will now proceed to add additional conceptual and methodological clarity to its components.
2 The four causes of emulation
Devising a four-causal account of emulation first requires dividing it into its component parts. To do this I appeal to and synthesise a number of relevant sources, primarily Aristotle’s four causes (Physics 1936, 94b21-35; Metaphysics 1999, 1044a32-4), the empirical virtue measurement literature (Morgan et al., 2017, p. 4; Wright et al., 2020, p. 8) and Kristjánsson’s componential account of virtuous emotions (2018, pp. 8-13). Regarding the latter, it should be noted that Kristjánsson – albeit briefly – proposes a four-causal account of virtuous emotions. I draw upon this for their temporal order – something Aristotle omitted – but due to my focus on virtue proper replace the final cause with virtuous action. Reimagined, Kristjánsson’s four causes of virtuous emotion encompass:
- the efficient cause: the ‘source’ of an emotion – perceptionthe formal cause: the ‘intentional object’ of an emotion – thought (cognition)
- the material cause: the ‘physiological valance’ of an emotion – physical feelings
- the final cause: the ‘goal directed activity’ of an emotion – behavioural suggestion.
Synthesised with the aforementioned influences, I then propose that the four causes of emulation comprise:
- the efficient cause: the moral agent’s perception of the role model’s virtues as representative of a moral ideal;
- the formal cause: the phronetically informed evaluation that these ideals are worthy of emulation and possible to acquire;
- the material cause: physically feeling the distress and admiration, associated with one’s lack of the desired quality, i.e., the role-model-represented ideal, which induces
the motivational state of inspiration; - the final cause: virtuous action concerning ends – putting the role-model-represented
ideal of virtue into practice.
Ultimately, reconstructing Aristotle’s four causes and applying them to the virtue of emulation enables me to explain it as a quadripartite causal process encompassing both virtuous emotion (the first three causes) and virtuous action (the final cause) – a process which helps one better understand how emulation works. It is worth noting here that in contrast to Zagzebski (2017), I accommodate admiration within just the material cause, understand it as merely a physiological feeling, and do not elevate it to the status of full-blown virtuous emotion. It is also worth noting that I have constructed and defended a full four-causal account of emulation (Henderson, 2023), yet for present purposes this deliberately brief nod to it will suffice.
3 Entangled phronesis
A further way in which my account represents a novel contribution to neo-Aristotelian character developmental theory concerns the introduction of a new concept: entangled phronesis. In short, entangled phronesis is the underlying psycho-moral mechanism which I suggest drives emulation by enabling a role model to rationally communicate with a learner in developmentally sensitive ways. The introduction of this concept enables me to overcome a potential objection to understanding emulation as a moral virtue, namely that due to Aristotle’s insistence that moral goodness ‘in the strict sense’ requires phronesis, and phronesis requires moral virtue (e.g., see 1936, NE, 1144b30–23), as moral learners have not yet acquired phronesis, appealing to emulation as a method of virtue development appears misguided.
Ultimately, adding entangled phronesis to the conceptual landscape of emulation renders this paradox specious. More precisely, since entangled phronesis concerns the role model as a substitute for phronesis, it enables the learner to be virtuous by association. I argue that the entangling process is developmentally sensitive, meaning that it works differently according to one’s degree of phronetic development. In one’s earliest years, I suggest that the role model’s phronesis directly supports elementary moral learners in the practice of ‘virtue’ even before their phronesis has begun to develop, primarily by encouraging and discouraging virtuous and vicious behaviour. This I call ‘habituated emulation’. From this phase follows a more sophisticated form of emulation where the role model’s phronesis and the learner’s emerging phronesis combine to stimulate virtuous action. This I call ‘complete emulation’. In this sense, emulation can be thought of as a two-step psycho-moral process which concerns the gradual development of both moral virtue and phronesis.
However, in light of the Aristotelian truism that pre-phronetic, i.e., non-rational, habituation is insufficient for full-virtue, since virtue entails one is in a certain— phronetically informed—state (1936, NE , pp. 1105a30–32; 1144a17–21), one may question the extent to which, particularly habituated, emulation can be considered virtuous. I argue that the role model’s substituted phronesis means that habituated emulation can be considered virtuous in a very weak and indirect sense. However, the virtuosity of complete emulation is somewhat more complicated, partly because once phronesis is fully developed, emulation becomes superfluous, since fully-developed phronesis enables a person to autonomously practice virtue, rather than doing so via the emulation of role models. Going beyond Aristotle’s own texts, I therefore propose that complete emulation should be understood as a virtue which, unlike other virtues, requires only developing, rather than fully-developed phronesis, because of its entangled association with the role model’s phronesis. This point also entails that emulation ought to be understood as a moral virtue which is explicitly associated with the sphere of moral education, and thus one which is practiced prior to other virtues, in order to acquire them.
Conclusion
In this paper, I proposed a reconstructed neo-Aristotelian four-causal account of emulation as a moral virtue. This conceptual framework, then enabled me to expound emulation as a two-step psycho-moral developmental process involving entangled phronesis. Implicit to this account is that role models must be good-enough phronomoi, meaning that they must have cultivated a sufficient amount of phronesis to enable it to entangle. This also implies that known, i.e., experientially available, role models best stimulate emulation, thus illuminating the normative importance of ordinary role models that the morally immature might encounter in their lives, such as their teachers. Having added considerable clarity to our understating of what emulation qua role modelling is and what it potentially involves, it would be tempting to here propose practical insights as to how it ought to manifest in a classroom or professional context. However, doing this with integrity requires first establishing that the concepts and mechanisms I propose in this paper are psychologically realistic (see Flanagan, 1991, p. 32) and developmentally adequate (see Lapsley, 2021, p. 138) – an endeavour which will comprise the next step in this emerging theory of emulation.
References
Aristotle. (1936). Aristotle’s physics: A revised text / with introduction and commentary by W.D. Ross. Clarendon Press.
https://doi.org/10.1093/actrade/9780198141099.book.1
Aristotle. (1999). Metaphysics / translated with a commentary by Arthur Madigan. Oxford University Press.
https://doi.org/10.1093/oseo/instance.00264022
Aristotle. (2001). Rhetoric / translated by W. Rhys Roberts. Virginia Tech.
Aristotle. (2009). Nicomachean ethics / translated by David Ross with introduction and notes by Lesley Brown (revised. ed.). Oxford University Press.
Croce, M. (2019). Exemplarism in moral education: Problems with applicability and indoctrination. Journal of Moral Education, 48(3), 291–302.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240.2019.1579086
Croce, M., & Vaccarezza, M. S. (2017). Educating through exemplars: Alternative paths to virtue. Theory and Research in Education, 15(1), 5–19.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1477878517695903
Curren, R., & Kotzee, B. (2014). Can virtue be measured? Theory and Research in Education, 12(3), 266–282.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1477878514545205
Flanagan, O. J. (1991). Varieties of moral personality: Ethics and psychological realism. Harvard University Press.
Fowers, B. J., Carroll, J. S., Leonhardt, N. D., & Cokelet, B. (2021). The emerging science of virtue. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 16(1), 118–147.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691620924473
Henderson, E. (2022). The educational salience of emulation as a moral virtue. Journal of Moral Education, 53(1), 1–16.
https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240.2022.2130882
Henderson, E. (2023). Entangled phronesis and the four causes of emulation: Developmental insights into role modelling. Theory and Research in Education, 21(3), 264–283.
https://doi.org/10.1177/14778785231203104
Irwin, T. H. (2015). II—Nil Admirari? Uses and abuses of admiration. Supplementary volume – Aristotelian Society, 89(1), 223–248.
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8349.2015.00251.x
Kaftanski, W. (2022). Admiration, affectivity, and value: Critical remarks on exemplarity. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 1–18.
Kristjánsson, K. (2006). Emulation and the use of role models in moral education. Journal of Moral Education, 35(1), 37–49.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240500495278
Kristjánsson, K. (2015). Aristotelian character education. Routledge.
https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315752747
Kristjánsson, K. (2018). Virtuous emotions (First edition. ed.). Oxford University Press.
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198809678.001.0001
Kristjánsson, K. (2020). Flourishing as the aim of education: A neo-Aristotelian view. Routledge.
https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429464898
Kristjánsson, K., Fowers, B., Darnell, C., & Pollard, D. (2021). Phronesis (practical wisdom) as a type of contextual integrative thinking. Review of General Psychology, 25(3), 239–257.
https://doi.org/10.1177/10892680211023063
Lapsley, D. (2021). The developmental science of phronesis. In M. De Caro & M. S. Vaccarezza (Eds.), Practical wisdom: Philosophical and psychological perspectives (pp. 138–159). Routledge.
Morgan, B., Gulliford, E., & Kristjánsson, K. (2017). A new approach to measuring moral virtues: The multi-component gratitude measure. Personality and Individual Differences, 107(1 March 2017), 179–189.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2016.11.044
Rorty, A. O. (1984). Aristotle on the metaphysical status of “pathe”. The Review of Metaphysics, 37(3), 521–546.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/20128048
Sanderse, W. (2013). The meaning of role modelling in moral and character education. Journal of Moral Education, 42(1), 28–42.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240.2012.690727
Steutel, J., & Spiecker, B. (2004). Cultivating sentimental dispositions through Aristotelian habituation. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 38(4), 531–549.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0309-8249.2004.00403.x
Szutta, N. (2019). Exemplarist moral theory – some pros and cons. Journal of Moral Education, 48(3), 280–290.
https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240.2019.1589435
Vaccarezza, M. S., & Niccoli, A. (2019). The dark side of the exceptional: On moral exemplars, character education, and negative emotions. Journal of Moral Education, 48(3), 332–345.
https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240.2018.1534089
Vaccarezza, M. S., & Niccoli, A. (2022). Let the donkeys be donkeys: In defense of inspiring envy. In S. Protasi (Ed.), The moral psychology of envy (pp. 111–128). Rowman & Littlefield.
https://doi.org/10.5771/9781538160077-111
Vos, P. H. (2018). Learning from exemplars: Emulation, character formation and the complexities of ordinary life. Journal of Beliefs & Values, 39(1), 17–28.
https://doi.org/10.1080/13617672.2017.1393295
Wright, J. C., Warren, M. T., & Snow, N. E. (2020). Understanding virtue: Theory and measurement. Oxford University Press.
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190655136.001.0001
Zagzebski, L. (2013). Moral exemplars in theory and practice. Theory and Research in Education, 11(2), 193–206.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1477878513485177
Zagzebski, L. (2015). Admiration and the admirable. Supplementary Volume – Aristotelian Society, 89, 205–221.
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8349.2015.00250.x
Zagzebski, L. T. (2017). Exemplarist moral theory. Oxford University Press.
https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190655846.001.0001
Recommended Citation
Henderson, E. (2024). Beyond admiration: Rethinking the nature of emulation qua role modelling. On Education. Journal for Research and Debate, 7(19).
https://doi.org/10.17899/on_ed.2024.19.4
Do you want to comment on this article? Please send your reply to editors@oneducation.net. Replies will be processed like invited contributions. This means they will be assessed according to standard criteria of quality, relevance, and civility. Please make sure to follow editorial policies and formatting guidelines.